@o_o@programming.dev asked “why are folks so anti-capitalist?” not long ago. It got quite a few comments. But I noticed a trend: a lot of people there didn’t agree on the definition of “capitalism”.
And the lack of common definition was hobbling the entire discussion. So I wanted to ask a precursor question. One that needs to be asked before anybody can even start talking about whether capitalism is helpful or good or necessary.
Main Question
- What is capitalism?
- Since your answer above likely included the word “capital”, what is capital?
- And either,
- A) How does capitalism empower people to own what they produce? or, (if you believe the opposite,)
- B) How does capitalism strip people of their control over what they produce?
Bonus Questions (mix and match or take them all or ignore them altogether)
- Say you are an individual who sells something you create. Are you a capitalist?
- If you are the above person, can you exist in both capitalist society and one in which private property has been abolished?
- Say you create and sell some product regularly (as above), but have more orders than you can fulfill alone. Is there any way to expand your operation and meet demand without using capitalist methods (such as hiring wage workers or selling your recipes / process to local franchisees for a cut of their proceeds, etc)?
- Is the distinction between a worker cooperative and a more traditional business important? Why is the distinction important?
That’s not frustration. The viewpoint you are describing (that workers are not allowed to own what they produce) actually comes from a different definition of “capital” and “capitalism” than the one you are using. And that difference in definitions is why I created this post. And I appreciate your answer. It lets me highlight the differences in definitions and the consequences of those differences. Because in the case of capitalism, the difference in definitions are actually more important than any difference in values or priorities.
You noted that people are saying “workers aren’t allowed to own what they produce in capitalism.” But those people are not referring to capitalism as you have defined it.
Capital
I’m sorry, but no one who disagrees with you thinks that the ability to accrue property and money deprive workers of control over what they produce. Not even Marx and Engels. Not even Mao or Stalin. Certainly, property and money can we wielded in such a way that they become capital. But until then, property and money are merely wealth.
The definition used by people like Marx and Engels – or by the entire field of economics – is: capital is property that allows or speeds up the production of goods. A mine. An oil rig. A McDonalds burger conveyor-belt-oven-thingy. A 3D printer. In other words, the word “capital” is about the function of the property. Not its value. A painting can cost $1,000,000 and still not become capital. Because no one will ever operate that painting to cook burgers. Or to mine ores.
Capitalism
Now “the ability to own commodity-producing property” is still not quite sufficient for a system to become “capitalism.” In fact, Marx and Engels didn’t want any capital to be destroyed at all in the overthrow of the bourgeoisie. Because even under the definition of “capital” that communists still to this day believe in, the existence of capital and ownership of it are still not inherently a source of coercion.
There’s another crucial piece to the puzzle that leads to people complaining about the whole system:
In capitalism as a system, some form of employment contract always allows the owner of capital to own everything produced using that capital.
For example, the oil rig owner – according to employment contracts – owns all of the oil produced using the oil rig. But not only did the owner not need to work the rig to extract the oil: the owner also did not need to weld the seams or turn the screws to build the oil rig. All the owner needs is official ownership of the oil rig and a system that acknowledges their right to everything the oil rig produces, (regardless of who needed to input their labor to turn the oil rig into anything other than a metal sculpture in the ocean.) and with those two things, they are entitled to all of the proceeds of the rig.
Now, hopefully, you can see that, provided a worker has entered into such a contract, “workers are not allowed to own what they produce” is not a statement born from frustration: it’s just true by definition. It’s not saying “the worker is NEVER allowed to own anything they ever create in this society.” It’s saying: “within the relationship laid out by the employment contract, the worker who operates capital is not entitled to the direct consequences of their labor.”
Now, whether the worker benefits from this arrangement is another picture, but in accepting an employment contract, the worker is entering into a dynamic where they do not own the outcome of their own labor.
Bonus Question #4
Which is why bonus question #4 (the difference between a workers’ cooperative and a company that uses these employment contracts) is extremely important to understanding the consequences of the difference between these definitions. You even touched on its importance in your earlier replies, saying yourself:
(Aside: what you’re describing here is literally Marx’s theory of alienation.) But more importantly,
I’m assuming the sprocket company “produces” sprockets by your definition of “produce.” Well, in a workers’ co-op, the workers vote in the decisions of the company. They elect the CEO (if there is one) and the managers. They take shares of the profits. They are the company. And if the workers are the company, and the company produces sprockets, then the workers are once again – just like if they were self-employed, but with the benefits of efficiency and networking that come from being part of an organization – producing sprockets. They are no longer (as Marx would say) alienated from the results of their labor.
In other words, the co-op is a form of self-employment according to the definitions you appear to be using. Which makes the distinction between cooperatives and other kinds of companies… massive.
The people saying, “capitalism strips workers of the results of their labor” love workers’ co-ops. Love them. Despite you probably defining the workers’ cooperative as “another example of capitalism”, not even avowed Marxists would in any circumstance suggest that the worker co-op “disallows workers from owning what they produce.” In fact, they strongly believe the opposite. To them (and to Marx himself) the worker cooperative operates under an entire opposing paradigm to the worker contract. And to them, it is therefore a rival philosophy to capitalism.
You don’t have to accept their definitions. You don’t need to believe Marxist definitions are correct. You can believe co-ops are capitalist all you want.
But please: try to understand that when people criticize “capitalism,” they are (I 100% guarantee) referring to something far more narrow and far more specific than what you call capitalism.
I get the sense I’ve touched a nerve here. Though I’m not sure where.
I would like to mention I never suggested the frustration comes from workers not being able to own anything at all. Though I still believe what you said about workers not being entitled to the direct consequences of their labor is flawed. Similar to someone saying “I spend all day pulling oil out of the ground, but I’m not allowed to own any of it”. That’s a fair complaint, and I’d suggest any oil rig worker who wants to get paid in oil should absolutely negotiate for that with their employer. What I was trying to explain is the “direct consequences of their labor” is the compensation they’re paid for providing said labor. You, as a worker, sell your labor for a price, same as any other transaction. If you will, your “sprocket” in this situation is the labor you provide.
I get that the worker is not the only reason the sprocket exists. I understand that he uses someone’s else alloy-pouring lava-pitcher to pour molten steel into a sprocket cast someone else owns. Whoever owns those things and consented / instructed for them to be used in the above manner shares responsibility (might even be more responsible) for the creation of that sprocket. But the sprocket still doesn’t exist until the worker poured the alloy.
The fact that the worker then didn’t create a sprocket, or produce a sprocket, or cause a sprocket to exist – is an alienating step only found in certain kinds of businesses. (And those are the only kinds of businesses anti-capitalists dislike).
For example, a worker can walk into a worker co-op, pour the same kind of alloy heated in the same kind of furnace into a cast that is shaped the exact same, but the worker at this co-op (unlike the worker for the private company) has now created a sprocket.
I’m pretty sure you would agree, right? Because he co-owns the company and he had a democratic voice in the acquisition of the company’s tools? He is responsible for all of the things that caused that sprocket to be created. No other factors were more involved than the worker-owner’s contributions and decisions.
So even though the co-op worker did the exact same thing using the exact same kinds of machinery as the private company worker, would you agree that the sprocket (which only existed after he poured the alloy) was a direct consequence of the co-op worker’s actions? (Whereas it was not a direct consequence of the private employee’s actions)
No. Both workers have created a sprocket, which exists as a direct result of their actions
The workers should not have to negotiate for their inalienable rights to appropriate the fruits of their labor, the moral basis for private property. A system that really defends private property should guarantee and secure their rights. You might respond that workers consent to give up their rights, but the rights are inalienable meaning they cannot be transferred even with consent. They’re inalienable because they follow from de facto responsibility, which can’t be given up even with consent